boundedness of movement

clause

a structure containing a (visible or invisible) subject and a predicate.

extraction site

the position from which elements move.

finite clause

a clause containing a finite verb.

landing site

the position elements move to.

Locality Restrictions on Movement

a head cannot move over the top of another head, a subject cannot move over the top of another subject – a constituent cannot move over the top of a like constituent. See also Relativized Minimality.

non-finite clause

a clause in which no finite verb is present.

object

a DP complement immediately following the verb. It can move to the subject position in passive sentences. See also direct object, indirect object.

predicate

the part of the clause excluding the subject giving information about the subject: Mary [is clever/likes chocolate/is waiting for Jamie/was in bed/is a university student].

raising

a process whereby the subject of an embedded infinitival clause moves to the subject position of the verb selecting the clause. In such structures the selecting verb is a one-argument verb selecting a clause (like seem). If the clause is non-finite, the subject of the embedded clause is not assigned Case within the clause, but since the subject position of the selecting verb is empty it can move there to be case-marked.

semantics

the study of meaning. It covers both lexical meaning and the meaning of sentences with special emphasis on their truth conditions (under what circumstances a sentence is true/false).

subject position

the position where subjects appear in the tree. The base position of the subject depends on its theta role. Agents and experiencers are generated in Spec,vP. Theme subjects appear in Spec,VP. These positions are not Case positions, so the subjects move to the canonical subject position, Spec, IP.

Basic English Syntax with Exercises

3.2.4 Locality Restrictions on movement

The restrictions on movement we have mentioned so far have concerned its structure preserving nature. Not all structures which conform to these restrictions are grammatical, however, indicating that other restrictions are in operation. Most of the movements we have looked at have involved something moving within a single clause. Passivisation, for example, moves the object of a predicate to the subject of that predicate and obviously both the extraction site and the landing site are within the same clause. There are movements however, that move elements from one clause to another. Consider the following:

(105)ait seems [Fiona favours dancing]
bFiona seems [to favour dancing]

Given the near synonymy of these two sentences and the fact that the subject of seem in (105b) does not appear to be semantically related to this verb (Fiona is not the one who ‘seems’) we might assume that the latter is formed by a movement of the lower clause subject into the higher clause subject position:

(106)

This movement is known as raising as the subject of the lower clause raises to the subject of a higher clause.

Raising can apparently happen out of a number of clauses:

(107)

Thus, at first sight it would seem that movement is unrestricted in terms of how far an element can be moved. But on closer inspection this might not be an accurate description of what is going on here. For example, note that in (107b) and (c) all the clauses that the subject is raised out of are non-finite and none of them seem to have subjects.

Suppose we try to move out of a finite clause instead:

(108)a*Stan1 seems [it is unlikely [t1 to steal diamonds]]
bit seems [Stan1 is unlikely [t1 to steal diamonds]]

As we can see, a subject can be raised out of a non-finite clause into the subject position of a finite clause, but it cannot be raised out of a finite clause. Note that the finite clause in (108a) has a subject of its own: it. It is a fact about English finite clauses that they must have subjects and hence the sentence would be ungrammatical if the subject were missing for independent reasons. So this case differs from the grammatical movement in (107c) in two ways: the moved subject is moved out of a finite clause and it is moved out of a clause with a subject.

To control for these variables, let us consider a case where the movement is out of a non-finite clause with a subject:

(109)ait is unusual [for Eric to hope [Stan will steal diamonds]]]
b*Stan1 is unusual [for Eric to hope [t1 to steal diamonds]]]

Again the result is ungrammatical, demonstrating that movement over a subject is itself enough to cause an ungrammaticality. But why would moving over a subject be a problem? If long distance movements are possible, it is hard to understand why the presence or absence of a subject should make any difference at all. However, if we suppose that long distance movements are not possible, though an element can move a long way via a series of short movements, we can come to an understanding of these observations. Consider the grammatical case of (107). As each subject position is empty it is possible for the moved subject to move into each one in turn, moving from one clause to the next each time:

(110)a[e] seems [[e] to be believed [[e] to be unlikely [Stan to steal diamonds]]]
b

If there is a subject in one of these positions the moving subject would be forced to make a longer movement and if long movements are not allowed, we predict the result to be ungrammatical, which it is:

(111)a[e] is unusual [for Eric to hope [Stan to steal diamonds]]]
b

We call this phenomenon, the boundedness of movement. For now it is enough to note that movement is bounded. We will look in more detail at the phenomenon in a subsequent chapter.