adjective

a constituent with the feature composition: [+N, +V, –F] modifying nouns, e.g. mad in mad cow. These constituents cannot have nominal complements, their semantically nominal complement must appear as a Prepositional Phrase with the rescue strategy of of-insertion.

agent

one of the thematic or theta-roles, where the argument deliberately performs an action, as Jamie in Jamie sang a song or Robert in Robert kicked the cat. In terms of the UTAH the agentive theta-role is assigned to the specifier position of vP, similarly to experiencer arguments.

arguments

the participants minimally involved in an action defined by the predicate. The complements and the subject, the latter also called an external argument.

compound noun

two nouns put together to form a single noun, e.g. homework.

count noun

a noun that shows number distinction, e.g. one book/two books.

derived noun

a noun derived from a word belonging to another word category. See deverbal noun.

deverbal noun

a noun derived from a verb, e.g. a bite from the verb to bite.

distribution

the set of positions that the grammar determines to be possible for a given category. Words that distribute in the same way will belong to the same categories, words that distribute differently will belong to different categories.

experiencer

one of the thematic or theta-roles where the argument experiences some physical or mental state, like Mary in Mary was afraid of dogs. The experiencer theta-role is assigned in the specifier position of vP, similarly to the agent role. If both an agent and an experiencer argument are selected by the verb there are two vPs projected and the experiencer occupies the specifier position of the lower vP.

[±F]

one of the three basic binary features on which all categories can be defined. With the help of these features we can explain why we have the categories that we do and also describe how these categories are related. With the help of the three binary features we can predict what kinds of categories are possible in human language, we can give an exclusive list of them. [±F] is a feature used to distinguish between functional and thematic categories. [–F] categories have thematic content and [+F] categories do not. The categories with [+F] feature are the following: inflections, complementisers, determiners and degree adverbs. Certain categories are unspecified for the [±F] feature, see underspecification.

irregular

cannot be described with the help of a rule, exceptional.

lexical entry

a collection of the idiosyncratic properties of lexical items.

mass noun

a noun that does not show number distinction, e.g. tea/a cup of tea. See also partitive construction.

[±N]

one of the three basic binary features on which all categories can be defined. With the help of these features we can explain why we have the categories that we do and also describe how these categories are related. With the help of the three binary features we can predict what kinds of categories are possible in human language, we can give an exclusive list of them. Since we want to define verbs and nouns as polar opposites the abstract binary features [±N] and [±V] were introduced, though obviously they do not mean noun and verb and are used to define other categories besides nouns and verbs. A property linked to the [–N] feature is the ability to have a nominal complement. The categories with [+N] feature are the following: a. thematic: nouns, adjectives; b. functional: determiners, degree adverbs; unspecified for the [F] value: post-determiners, measure nouns.

noun

a word that names people, places or things that can have a plural form. Feature composition: [+N, –V, –F]

number

a contrast between singular and plural as in a shirt/several shirts. The English regular plural marker is s.

partitive construction

if we want to count mass nouns we can do so by inserting an appropriate term expressing some unit of the given mass noun which will result in a partitive construction: two bars of chocolate, a glass of milk.

patient

one of the thematic or theta-roles where the argument is affected by the action described by the verb, e.g. in Peter stroked the cat the cat is directly affected by this activity.

plural noun

a noun denoting more than one entity, e.g. three teddy bears. Count nouns can be used either in the singular or the plural form.

predicate

the part of the clause excluding the subject giving information about the subject: Mary [is clever/likes chocolate/is waiting for Jamie/was in bed/is a university student].

preposition

a syntactic unit preceding its complement, the most often a DP defining a special syntactic and/or semantic relationship between the complement and another constituent: cat in the bag/grapes of wrath/tea without sugar/a reduction of taxes. Feature composition: [–F, –N, –V].

proper noun

a name, e.g. John, Wendy Smith, the Beatles. Within the DP it appears as an NP (as opposed to pronouns)

regular

can be described with the help of a rule, e.g. the regular plural form of nominal expressions is formed by adding the plural morpheme s.

semantics

the study of meaning. It covers both lexical meaning and the meaning of sentences with special emphasis on their truth conditions (under what circumstances a sentence is true/false).

singular noun

a noun denoting one entity, e.g. a teddy bear. Count nouns can be singular or plural.

subcategorisation frame

that part of the lexical entry that states the categorial status of the complement.

subcategory

a category under a main category, e.g. the category of intransitive verbs is a subcategory of the verbal category.

theme

one of the thematic roles where the argument is not affected by the action described by the verb e.g. in Peter saw John nothing directly happens to John as a result of being seen. In terms of the UTAH the theme theta-role is assigned to the specifier position of the VP.

there-construction: see existential there-construction.

theta-grid

that part of a predicate’s lexical entry which informs us about what theta-roles the predicate has.

theta role

the semantic role of the participants as required by the predicate. E.g. verbs define what kind of semantic relationship is to be established between the verb itself and the arguments of the verb, and arguments are selected accordingly. The verb kick calls for an agent subject, so its subject position cannot be occupied by e.g. my CD-player.

[±V]

one of the three basic binary features on which all categories can be defined. With the help of these features we can explain why we have the categories that we do and also describe how these categories are related. With the help of the three binary features we can predict what kinds of categories are possible in human language, we can give an exclusive list of them. Since we want to define verbs and nouns as polar opposites the abstract binary features [±N] and [±V] were introduced, though obviously they do not mean noun and verb and are used to define other categories besides nouns and verbs. The categories with [±V] feature are the following: a. thematic: verbs, prepositions; b. functional: inflections, degree adverbs, aspectual auxiliaries; unspecified for the [F] value: aspectual auxiliaries, post-determiners.

Basic English Syntax with Exercises

1.3.4.2 Nouns

The next category we will discuss is the noun, which we categorised as bearing the features [–F, +N, –V] above. With verbs, they share the property that they have Θ-grids as part of their lexical entries, being [–F] categories. But they are distinguished from verbs on the other two features and hence do not share many other properties.

From a morphological point of view, nouns are less varied than verbs, having just two forms, singular and plural:

(80)dogdogs
passpasses
mousemice
buffalobuffalo
cherubcherubim

Like verbs there is a fair amount of deviation from the regular morphological representation of the plural [s]. Again, we will ignore the morphological irregularities and treat these forms as being syntactically stem + plural:

(81)dog + s= dogs
pass + s= passes
mouse + s= mice
buffalo + s= buffalo
cherub + s= cherubim

Besides morphological irregularity, there are also a number of problematic cases. Some nouns express concepts for which number distinctions are not normally made. For example, sand refers to stuff that naturally comes in a quantity for which the division into ‘one’ (singular) and ‘more than one’ (plural) is not particularly natural. Nouns which naturally accommodate this distinction are known as count nouns and those that do not are called mass nouns. If we wish to individuate mass nouns, we usually do this in terms of another noun which names a unit of what the mass noun refers to and put this into a more complicated construction, known as the partitive:

(82)athree grains of sand
bseven loaves of bread
ctwo cups of tea

Thus, it is not typical to find plural forms of mass nouns, though, of course, this does not mean that they should not be considered as nouns. As a matter of fact, plural forms of mass nouns do exist, though their uses tend to be rather specialised:

(83)athe sands of time
bthe seven seas
cthe breads that we bake

Typically, the plural forms of mass nouns tend to refer to different collections of what the nouns refer to. Take (83c) for example. Here the plural noun breads refers to various types of bread: cottage loaves, whole meal bread, rye bread, baguettes, etc.

Another class of nouns for which the plural form is not entirely natural is the proper nouns, i.e. names. Again, there is probably a semantic reason for this: names name individuals and individuals come in ones. Once again it is possible to find proper nouns used in the plural with the right semantic context:

(84)athe two Ronnies (British comedy series of the 1970s)
bthe Smiths will be visiting next week
cthere are no Einsteins in this class

In the first case, the plural proper noun is used because it refers to two individuals who happen to have the same name (Ronny Corbet and Ronny Barker in this instance). In the second, the family name Smith is used in the plural to refer to the collective set of individuals of that family and in the third case the name Einstein is not used as a name at all, but as a word to describe an individual with certain properties (high intelligence in this case).

Exactly the opposite problem is caused by examples such as scissors and trousers, which appear to be nouns which lack a singular form (*scissor, *trouser). This might be more of a semantic problem rather than a grammatical one however, as the objects to which these words refer are inherently plural in some respect: scissors have two blades and trousers have two legs. Moreover, without this plural aspect to the meaning, the object ceases to be describable in the same way: something with one blade cannot be described as scissors (or scissor for that matter) and something with one leg is not trousers (nor trouser). Again, it is possible to find the singular form of such words used, though in very limited contexts. When two nouns are put together to form a single compound noun, the preceding noun must be in its singular form:

(85)armchair*armschair
doorframe*doorsframe
schoolboy*schoolsboy

(There are some exceptions, e.g. dogsbody.) Note this restriction holds whether or not the plural form would be more appropriate semantically, as is the case with armchair which tend to have more than one arm! When an inherently plural noun is used as the first noun in a compound, it too appears in its singular form:

(86)scissor-kick*scissors-kick
trouser-press*trousers-press
spectacle-case*spectacles-case

In general then, it seems that nouns are a fairly well behaved category and that even for the more problematic cases morphologically distinct forms for singular and plural can be found.

Turning to the distribution of nouns, as with verbs a proper treatment of this will be possible later in this chapter, though we can once again talk about subcategories of noun. Nouns subcategorise in exactly the same way that verbs do, in terms of restrictions placed on the possible categories of their complements. Just as with verbs, the complement of the noun follows it. The similarity between noun complements and verb complements can best be seen by comparing the behaviour of nouns that have been derived from verbs with these verbs:

(87)ahe waited for the letterhis wait for the letter
bhe believed in Father Christmashis belief in Father Christmas
che fought with the dragonhis fight with the dragon
dI expect that he leftmy expectation that he left
ethey detonated the bombtheir detonation of the bomb

As seems clear, most nouns that are formed from verbs take exactly the same complements as the original verb does. The one difference can be seen in (87e) where the verb takes a nominal complement while the noun takes a prepositional one. Note that the verb and its complement express exactly the same relationship as the noun and its complement: in both cases it is ‘the bomb’ that gets detonated. Thus, the preposition of in the case of the noun complement does not seem to add anything of a semantic nature. Moreover, this is an entirely regular process – any verb that has a nominal complement will take a prepositional complement (with of) when it is formed into a noun:

(88)construct a houseconstruction of a house
destroy his confidencedestruction of his confidence
observe the reactionobservation of the reaction
peruse the indexperusal of the index

Indeed, there are no nouns that take following nominal complements, even ones that are not formed from verbs:

(89)a book of magic*a book magic
a plague of flies*a plague flies
a case of mismanagement*a case mismanagement
a cup of tea*a cup tea

For some reason then, it seems that the whole class of nouns fails to have nominal complements and thus they differ from verbs in this way (we will see later on in this book there is an explanation for this observation). However, other than this, nouns can take any other kind of complement and as such we can propose that they subcategorise in the same way as verbs do, by the inclusion of a subcategorisation frame in their lexical entries.

This inability to take nominal complements is something nouns share with adjectives, as we shall see. Verbs pattern with prepositions in this respect. Thus we can claim that whatever property it is that allows verbs and prepositions to take nominal complements, it is connected to the [–N] feature that they both share. The [+N] categories (nouns and adjectives) obviously lack this property.

It is clear from the examples given above that nouns formed from verbs have arguments in the same way that those verbs do: the noun wait may express the relationship between someone who is waiting and what they are waiting for. The argument that comes to the left of the verb is typically expressed by the possessor of the derived noun (his and my and their in (87)). In other instances, however, the possessor simply names the one who possesses the noun. The difference is made clear in the two interpretations of the following:

(90)Ken’s construction of a kite

This can be interpreted either as something that Ken did (he constructed a kite) or something that he possesses (the kite is his). Obviously the possessive interpretation is only available for the case of the noun, the related verb cannot have a possessive argument:

(91)Ken constructed a kite

In this example, Ken can only be interpreted as agent. The question arises as to whether the possessor is another thematic argument which nouns can have, in addition to agents, patients, themes, goals, etc., or whether it is something of a different nature. There is reason to believe that the possessor is not the same kind of element as a thematic argument. One thing that differentiates possessors from other arguments is that the possessor may appear with almost any noun and does not appear to be determined by the noun’s meaning:

(92)amy music(e.g. the CDs that I own)
byour drawing(the one on your wall)
chis organisation(the one that belongs to him)
dour plans(the bits of paper that we have)

Of course there are things named by nouns that cannot be possessed in this way:

(93)Emily’s embarrassment

In this example, Emily has to be interpreted as the one who experiences the embarrassment rather than someone who possesses it outside of their emotions. But this is a general semantic fact: some things can be possessed and other things cannot. The fact remains, however, that of those things that are able to be possessed, the relationship between them and the possessor is uniform and is not affected by the meaning of the noun. This is very different from other argumentpredicate relationships:

(94)ahe wriggled(he = agent)
bhe arrived(he = theme)
che embarrasses easily(he = experiencer)
dhe attracts criticism(he = goal)

Another difference between the possessor and arguments is that the semantic relationship that possessors express is rather vague in relation to those expressed by arguments. Consider the following:

(95)Shufflebotham’s sheep

The relationship between Shufflebotham and the sheep could be almost anything, ranging from ownership to something far more distant such as the sheep that Shufflebotham selected in a sheep of the year contest. Thematic arguments, on the other hand, have very definite interpretations: an agent is someone who consciously performs an action and cannot be interpreted as anything else.

A final difference between possessors and arguments is that the possessor relationship is restricted to nouns whereas thematic relationships seem to be available to all thematic categories: we can find themes, experiencers, etc. for verbs, nouns or adjectives.

For these reasons, therefore, we will not consider the possessor to be a thematic role included in the lexical entry of the nouns, but something that can be added to any compatible noun. Below we can see some example lexical entries for nouns:

(96)waitcategory: [–F, +N, –V]
Θ-grid:<agent,goal>
subcat:[prepositional]
beliefcategory: [–F, +N, –V]
Θ-grid:<experiencer,theme>
subcat:[prepositional]
fightcategory: [–F, +N, –V]
Θ-grid:<agent,theme>
subcat:[prepositional]
expectationcategory: [–F, +N, –V]
Θ-grid:<experiencer,proposition>
subcat:[sentential]
plaguecategory: [–F, +N, –V]
Θ-grid:<theme>
subcat:[prepositional]
catcategory: [–F, +N, –V]
Θ-grid:<Ø>
subcat:[Ø]
20;-grid:<experiencer,proposition> subcat:[sentence]

There is no traditional term specifically for predicates with sentential complements, but generative grammar has not felt the need to invent one as the subcategorisation frame serves to distinguish between the different subcategories of verbs.